« Anne Applebaum takes on NYC | Main | Not auspicious »

My first intentional reading of a Columbia academic's work: Kendall Thomas' Racial Justice: Moral or Political?

(I warn you, this is easily the longest entry to date, and is both a bit rambling and less-focused than it would be if it were an answer to an assignment. Read at your own risk, and if you feel like being vitriolic in your comments realize I may just ignore you. :) )

In the process of reading Looking Back at Law's Century, I've just finished Kendall Thomas's article Racial Justice: Moral or Political. It causes me to worry some that the political content of my law degree may be more than I can handle, but then, it's not coursework. Thomas spends most of his article contending that the primary justification for or against a racial interpretation of our Constitution has been moral, but that a more expressly political interpretation is more appropriate.

As an argument goes, it makes sense so long as you accept the fundamental premise: that a moral interpretation of the constitution, whether it is right or not to allow laws which discriminate on the basis of race, have limitations in their normative value. While it's not the whole of his article, I'm most interested in his justification for a political view of racial justice due to the effects of law upon supposed racial 'civic publics.'

According to Thomas (to paraphrase crudely here, in the interest of space), it would be better to consider laws to be racially biased in terms of their political effects, than to concentrate on the moral rights or wrongs of laws which are 'colour-blind' or 'colour conscious.' His major example is the crack/powder cocaine disparity in sentencing in the United States, and he spends several pages contrasting his conception of the policy with another academic, the apparently conservative (or neo-liberal) Randall Kennedy.

Thomas reasons that because many states have laws disenfranchising convicted felons for life, the disparity in sentencing between crack-convicts and powder-convicts hurts 'black civic publics' by reducing both their political efficacy and coherency. [1] But this presupposes the existence of 'black civic publics' that are distinct from their white counterparts. [2] In a note, he proceeds at length to argue that this is not the case, and that individual black citizens should have the ability to leave the 'enclaves of resistance' that he claims these policies weaken through disenfranchisement. However, without this notion of a fairly unified black polity, his argument falls to pieces.

The concept that blacks (or other races) share a political culture may describe political reality today[3], but it is not the necessary political reality, merely what may have occurred because of our current space in history. The idea that any polity to which a standard middle-class black American (the stereotypical 'Huxtable') belongs is weakened by the disenfranchisement of dealer of crack or powdered cocaine presupposes that this person has more political interests in common with the criminal with which he shares a race, rather than his fellow businessmen, professionals, or academics across the racial divide. (The opposite also applies: a white powdered cocaine dealer is assumed to have more in common with a white minister than with his fellow dealer across the colour divide.)

Thomas then goes so far as to say that this common 'political culture' crosses 'racial cultures', and uses as an example New York City:

By way of a concrete example, consider the dynamics of black civic public life in the city in which I live, New York. Black people from the U.S. South, the Caribbean, Central and South America, Europe, and Africa have mobilized around an alternative, activist vision of racial justice in the urban polity. These black counterpublics have addressed issues from police brutality to environmental justice to the politics of race and representation in the city's cultural institutions. An oppositional black public presence in New York City has not required suppression of the myriad cultural (or class) differences among its constituent groups. This is because the political identity of these black urban counterpublics in no way entails the claim of a singular cultural identity. Rather, collective political action by black civic publics in New York City has stemmed from the recognition of a common location in the network of the city's racialized power relations.(102)

But New York City, with a history of racialized politics more extreme than the norm within the United States as a whole, is a bit of an odd example. Besides, constitutional rights span city boundaries (in which races may, by dint of propinquity due to de-facto segregation, be more politically homogenous) to encompass the nation. Besides which, New York City remains one in which politics apportions an appreciable percentage of the spoils of everyday life, and in which de facto segregation not just of races but of ethnic groups ('Little Italy,' etc.) isquite common. The combination of governmentally-apportioned spoils providing stakes and segregated neighborhoods providing opportunity promotes racially-conscious polities, and relatively few forces are working against this concentration. I wonder if Thomas supposes that a national 'black civic public' including individuals from not only cities but suburbs and countryside is sufficiently politically homogenous that a political interpretation of racial justice could be found. Would policies that help the 'black civic public' to which the discriminated-against crack-dealers belong also avail black business leaders and entrepreneurs?

Of course, the political difference I have with Thomas here extends to a conception of the law: whether it is a tool for use in politics, or the rules by which the political game is played. I have always thought of constitutional law as providing a channel within which politics may run, the 'banks of the river' which contain acceptable methods while remaining neutral to their results. My major concern with a political conception of racial justice comes from my economic studies and my thoughts on general systems: what you allow as the boundaries of a system both constrain the possible results and promote the likely ones. Thomas's recommendations of construing racial justice in a political manner do not only ensure that a racial polity may exist, but by providing obvious advantages to members of such a polity against others outside it, ensure that it always shall exist, or at least goes a long way towards promoting its survival against other possible outcomes.

By way of illustration, I'd point to a commonly cited criticism of the Bush administration's preferred alternative to affirmative action. In Texas, a certain percentage of the top graduates from all public high schools are ensured a place in the Texas higher-education system. The New York Times, among others, has pointed out that this system can only be considered effective in helping minority enrollment so long as a de facto segregation of the public schools exists. [4]

If you hold with the Times editorial page, this is a sign of racism, or at least bull-headed 'colour-blindness' in action. But to a system-thinker, it makes sense as a remedy. If the idea is that minorities are disadvantaged due to unequal access to high-quality public primary and secondary education (due to poverty, lack of English skills, or whatever), then this solution will be racially remedial so long as that segregation exists. If that segregation ends, it will be remedial towards anyone with such limited access, but cease to be racially remedial. As a systems policy, it's near-perfect--limited to those suffering from the identified problem up until the point that the problem no longer exists, while providing a method for eventually phasing out both problem and solution. Of course, it doesn't provide a total remedy (a minority group may be disproportionately affected by other factors than location), but then other policy prescriptions may be put forward for those problems, rather than a 'one-size-fits-all' race remedy.

Similarly, if a minority is disproportionately affected by poverty, than any policy which alleviates the effects of poverty will be disproportionately ameliorative to that minority. It strikes me that by institutionalising 'black' (or other minority) polities, these political thinkers miss a pretty important trick. If one can consider crack/powder distinctions in sentencing to be racist in a 'bad' way, even if the law itself applies equally to any race, then one can consider anti-poverty legislation (for instance, redistributive taxes, union rights, etc.) to be racially-biased in a 'good' way.

This provides a space for minority political leaders to put themselves at the forefront of political movements without having to pigeonhole themselves into being concerned with 'race' issues. The benefit, for instance, of a +20 point advantage to anyone from a disadvantaged family background applying to the University of Michigan might be roughly equivalent for members of racial minorities, or perhaps a +30 point benefit would be needed. In any event, even a larger point increase would be easier to justify both politically and judicially, and by gaining allies outside a self-defined racial 'polity,' it would become much easier to achieve. [5] The fact that members of a race at the moment have a number of shared political interests by no means implies that they must do so forever, and I would say that the purpose of law is to encourage change such that race is less of a motivating factor, rather than enshrining it as a necessary polity. By removing themselves from polities explicitly bounded by race, politicians would have the ability to advocate change as leaders of true 'rainbow coalitions,' as well as reducing the resistance encountered from those who continue to consider racial justice a moral, as well as political, issue.

[1] Since this isn't a formal essay, I fully realise that I'm simplifying his argument here. Few of my readers want a twelve page summary, and I don't intend to provide it. If you're interested, I strongly recommend the article, which is thought-provoking.
[2] Indeed, much of his argument's strength would seem to suppose the existence of 'white civic publics' sharing similar political ambitions, particularly in opposing 'black civic publics.' This unstated homogenity is to me one of the weak points of race-identity politics: the assumption of the monolithic 'Them.' When a poor rural Southern white speaks of the government that is 'giving all the jobs to those minorities' (and who is perhaps a target of old campaign ads by Jesse Helms), he's cursing largely the same power structure as a minority activist protesting crack/powder sentencing laws.
[3] I say may because I wouldn't concede this point, except in as much that as a voting block blacks as a race are predominantly Democratic. I somehow doubt this is a sufficient condition, though.
[4] It is important to note here that this is not an argument Thomas makes in his article, but merely one I think is similar to his thesis.
[5] Consider, for instance, the racial spoils system in the University of California, which at least in the public consciousness for a number of years advantaged blacks as a minority over Asians. A 'race neutral' policy would have allowed leaders to share alliances with anti-poverty groups across the racial divide, instead of the kind of antipathy which eventually led to a 'race-blind' referendum.

Comments

I can assure you that you are the first person--ever, in fact--to *intentionally* read a law review article . . .
This *is* a diary site. While I'll admit that the title can be ambiguously construed[1], it's meant to mean the first time I've intentionally sought out and read a Columbia academic's work. But never let it be said I'm not willing to compromise--I've changed the title for your benefit. On the other hand, whilst he's already dead, you might wish to inform Keat's estate that he made a similar error in construction, and the error should be corrected to avoid confusion. Still, you obviously didn't read the piece anyway--it's not from a law journal, but a collection in a book. [1] For those reading after the change of title, the original was 'First Intentional Reading of a Columbia Academic's Work..."
Hmm, have to say I read it quickly and followed not all of it but... Are you seriously contending that the law is not political (which it is) or just saying that it shouldn't be (which would be nice)? As for the whole community / polity / whatever thing I suspect we're so far apart that this isn't worth starting. M
Of course I'm not saying that the law isn't political--in many senses it clearly isn't. But you know me: it's all about the system. The law is one part of a political system, and I believe that system works best when as much as possible is run through the deliberative process of a legislature. The law, particularly constitutional law, constrains the outcomes that you can achieve, and I think that Thomas's proposal for how to view constitutional law with relation to race enshrines racial politics: by placing in the system advantages for the creation of racial, rather than issue-based, politics, you ensure they persist. At least that's what I hope I was saying. :)
... well, there is a problem with your proposition: "his provides a space for minority political leaders to put themselves at the forefront of political movements without having to pigeonhole themselves into being concerned with 'race' issues. The benefit, for instance, of a +20 point advantage to anyone from a disadvantaged family background applying to the University of Michigan might be roughly equivalent for members of racial minorities, or perhaps a +30 point benefit would be needed. In any event, even a larger point increase would be easier to justify both politically and judicially, and by gaining allies outside a self-defined racial 'polity,' it would become much easier to achieve. [5] The fact that members of a race at the moment have a number of shared political interests by no means implies that they must do so forever, and I would say that the purpose of law is to encourage change such that race is less of a motivating factor, rather than enshrining it as a necessary polity. By removing themselves from polities explicitly bounded by race, politicians would have the ability to advocate change as leaders of true 'rainbow coalitions,' as well as reducing the resistance encountered from those who continue to consider racial justice a moral, as well as political, issue" Most affirmative action slots go to members of racial elites, not those suffering the effects of racial discrimination. As a result, they violently oppose any system that is aimed at helping those who are disadvantaged. Some real dynamics there. You have two kinds of racial politics: (a) programs aimed at improving power bases by catering to (mostly non-voting) masses of the disinfranchised and (b) programs aimed at providing advantages to the racial elites within the community. Hmm, seems like the same way the Republicans work (vouchers for the masses, contracts for the rich) ... so it isn't unique to any group, but it gets in the way of systems that would actually work.
Is this like a guestbook?
Law profs like to force their students to learn the hard way. They never come straight to the point and spend a lot of time requiring students to study cases so that they come to understand the major legal issues via extensive reading rather than memorization. All law school text books are written this way as well. After law school almost all students take the BARBRI to prepare for the BAR exam. BARBRI focuses on all the main points that you learned in law school but rather than making it as painful as possible, it makes it as easy as possible. What took hundreds of hours of reading to understand in law school is sometimes spelled out in 30 pages of text. The whole format is much easier to learn. I highly recommend that anyone who is going to law school get a copy of last years BARBRI study books. Study them as you go through law school in tandum with your regular course work. You will know what your professors are getting at without having to go through their whole backwards education process. Of course you will still need to do all the reading and homework, but you will know what the point is. I think law students who do this will learn just as much as other students and perhaps more but with far less stress, frustration and sleepless nights. Why do law schools teach the way that they do? Well they do not want the law to be easy. They do not want the bar to be low. They want to create a barrier between the common man and the legal profession. They want a high drop out rate and they also want people who finally make it into the profession to feel important, like they have achieved something super human. If they came right out and told everyone what they really needed to know to pass the bar, law schools really would be run more like vocational colleges. The law profession attaches a great amount of self importance to itself, people in it want to really beleive that there is something more than just memorization to becoming a lawyer. What they refuse to acknoledge is that the importance in law is in how one practices it, not in how one passes the bar.
very nice site!
very nice site!
very nice site!

Post a comment

(If you haven't left a comment here before, you may need to be approved by the site owner before your comment will appear. Until then, it won't appear on the entry. Thanks for waiting.)

NOTICE TO SPAMMERS, COMMENT ROBOTS, TRACKBACK SPAMMERS AND OTHER NON-HUMAN VISITORS: No comment or trackback left via a robot is ever welcome at Three Years of Hell. Your interference imposes significant costs upon me and my legitimate users. The owner, user or affiliate who advertises using non-human visitors and leaves a comment or trackback on this site therefore agrees to the following: (a) they will pay fifty cents (US$0.50) to Anthony Rickey (hereinafter, the "Host") for every spam trackback or comment processed through any blogs hosted on threeyearsofhell.com, morgrave.com or housevirgo.com, irrespective of whether that comment or trackback is actually posted on the publicly-accessible site, such fees to cover Host's costs of hosting and bandwidth, time in tending to your comment or trackback and costs of enforcement; (b) if such comment or trackback is published on the publicly-accessible site, an additional fee of one dollar (US$1.00) per day per URL included in the comment or trackback for every day the comment or trackback remains publicly available, such fee to represent the value of publicity and search-engine placement advantages.

Giving The Devil His Due

And like that... he is gone (8)
Bateleur wrote: I tip my hat to you - not only for ... [more]

Law Firm Technology (5)
Len Cleavelin wrote: I find it extremely difficult to be... [more]

Post Exam Rant (9)
Tony the Pony wrote: Humbug. Allowing computers already... [more]

Symbols, Shame, and A Number of Reasons that Billy Idol is Wrong (11)
Adam wrote: Well, here's a spin on the theory o... [more]

I've Always Wanted to Say This: What Do You Want? (14)
gcr wrote: a nice cozy victorian in west phill... [more]

Choose Stylesheet

What I'm Reading

cover
D.C. Noir

My city. But darker.
cover
A Clockwork Orange

About time I read this...


Shopping

Projects I've Been Involved With

A Round-the-World Travel Blog: Devil May Care (A new round-the-world travel blog, co-written with my wife)
Parents for Inclusive Education (From my Clinic)

Syndicated from other sites

The Columbia Continuum
Other Blogs by CLS students